Integrative Veterinary Cancer Care: Are Claims without Evidence Dishonest?

One of the most frustrating problems with the promotion of alternative medicine and approaches that have not been validated through appropriate scientific testing is that proponents often feel free to make sweeping claims about safety and efficacy despite the
absence of evidence to support these. Personal experience, tradition, or
suggestive pre-clinical research are touted as “proof” of these claims, rather than as the suggestive but poorly reliable bits of evidence they actually are.

Responsible, science-based practitioners are ethically bound to acknowledge the imitations in our knowledge and in the evidence supporting our practices (though being imperfect human beings, of course we may sometimes fall short in this). But practitioners
of alternative approaches can much more aggressively market their practices
beyond the claims justified by good research data, either because they accept
anecdote, intuition, tradition, and personal experience as sufficient evidence,
or sometimes because they disdain the whole epistemological enterprise of mainstream science.

Unfortunately, pet owners and other consumers of veterinary products and services don’t generally evaluate the validity of medical claims from a rigorously evidence-based perspective. In fact, a survey published in the journal Integrative Cancer Therapies, found that scientific evidence was not highly valued by cancer patients investigating
alternative medicine and that anecdotes, information from friends or the Internet, and other sources with low reliability were more highly valued.

Of course, this shouldn’t be surprising. I don’t have the knowledge or expertise to effectively evaluate the competing claims of rival economists, art critics, or automobile mechanics, and we shouldn’t expect every human patient or pet owner to be an expert on
medicine, statistics, epistemology, or the other areas of knowledge and training required to evaluate the evidence and determine the validity of scientific hypotheses and medical claims. That is, after all, our job as doctors. There is a strong ethical duty on the part of doctors to communicate the true state of the evidence for therapies their patients or clients might choose.

However, if we neglect to take this responsibility seriously and accept lower-quality standards of evidence as sufficient, the claims we make are going to be just as persuasive to our clients as those that are actually founded on high-quality scientific evidence.
There is, in fact, a significant advantage to being unconstrained by the limitations and inevitable ambiguities and complexities of scientific evidence when making claims about our treatments. If the only basis needed to claim your interventions work better than anybody else’s is that you believe they do, you are free to say about anything and say it with confidence!

A classic example of this is the blog of a prominent advocate for “integrative” veterinary medicine. This veterinarian makes extensive use of the “bait and switch” approach to
marketing alternative therapies. He advocates many conventional treatments and
then adds unproven “natural” therapies to these. Any positive outcomes are credited to the added natural therapies, rather than the conventional treatment or normal individual variation among patients. However, negative outcomes, such as cancer developing despite the use of natural remedies promoted as protective, are never cited as evidence that the unconventional therapies might not be effective. The whole package is aggressively promoted as superior to conventional therapy, which is denigrated whenever possible. Here is an example:

About 40 years ago, President Nixon declared war on cancer. His goal was to find a cure for this horrible disease. Sadly, we are no closer to reaching that goal today than we
were 40 years ago. In most cases…we really haven’t done a better job of treating or curing cancer. While it is true that survival rates have increased, this is mainly due to early diagnosis. People and pets with Stage 3 or Stage4 metastatic cancer rarely survive.

The situation is no better for our pets. While treatment protocols have changed over the last 40 years, most pets with cancer are expected to only live 6 to 12 months following
diagnosis, and that’s ONLY if owners spend thousands of dollars treating the pet with surgery, radiation, and chemotherapy.

The good news is that using an integrative approach changes these sobering facts and statistics. Designing individualized treatment protocols for each person or pet with cancer,
incorporating a proper diet, nutritional supplements, and other natural therapies offers a much better prognosis for the cancer patient. We now have large volumes of research to show exactly how these natural therapies work in killing cancer and extending the lives of cancer patients.

In my own practice, the average pet with cancer, given a prognosis of 6 to 12 months of life
expectancy from conventional veterinarians, typically lives 12 to 24 months or even longer. Additionally, many pets with “incurable” cancers are cured from their cancers using an integrative approach to boost the pet’s immune system, kill cancer cells, reduce the spread of cancer, and detoxify the patient.

The world of integrative oncology offers much hope for the cancer patient. Integrative
doctors are helping people and pets with cancer live longer lives and in many cases curing cancers that are still considered incurable by conventional medicine.

…After surgery cuts out most of the cancer, and chemotherapy kills most of the cancer, and radiation burns most of the cancer, what’s left to do destroy any remaining
cancer cells? Absolutely nothing! Unless the patient continues therapy, using a combination of proper diet, mind-body medicine, and nutritional supplements, any cancer cells that have survived conventional therapy will, at some point, continue to grow, spread, and ultimately kill the patient.

The sad news is that so many cancer patients will ultimately die after surviving conventional therapies because nothing is done to prevent the recurrence of cancer…not one of these patients is doing anything “natural” to support her immune system or continue the fight against cancer once conventional therapies have finished. How sad and tragic to know that many people will needlessly die out of ignorance once their cancer returns.

…In my own veterinary practice, while I can never offer guarantees to my patients, I tell them that based upon my years of using natural therapies to help pets with cancer, I expect my patients to live one and a half to two times longer than their conventional doctors expect them to live IF they will use properly prescribed natural therapies.

So what are the general messages in this article?

 

1. Conventional medicine has made almost no meaningful progress in cancer treatment in the last 40 years.

2. Conventional therapy is icky (cutting, burning, and killing), expensive, and ultimately not very effective since most pets die of their cancer anyway after less than a year.

3. An “integrative” approach adding “natural” therapies to conventional treatment can
reliably help patients live up to twice as long as those treated conventionally, and can frequently cure cancers when mainstream medicine cannot.

Despite the reference to “large volumes of research” supporting these claims, none is provided in this article. The first claim is obviously and demonstrably untrue. The second consists of an attempt to derogate life-saving therapies by describing them in hostile
language combined with a falsehood. And the third claim is merely opinion with no reliable evidence supporting it.

Clearly, the burden of proving medical claims that are not generally accepted by the medical profession properly falls on the person making the claims. The absence of any effort to support these statements and implications with any evidence beyond personal opinion is a deliberate choice reflecting the author’s lack of interest in careful scientific
demonstration of the value of the therapies he recommends. While I do not intend to do the work of collecting and evaluating the research evidence for this author, I will point out some of the clear factual errors and (deliberate?) misstatements he makes.

1. We haven’t made any significant progress in cancer treatment in 40 years.

This is common claim on the part of those promoting alternative cancer therapies is patently false and has been debunked extensively elsewhere (e.g. A New Perspective on the War on Cancer, which reviews a book on the subject, the Emperor of All Maladies: A Biography of Cancer). Cancer has become a prominent cause of death as people have stopped dying as soon and often from infectious diseases, trauma, malnutrition and many of the other causes of mortality that science and science-based medicine has dramatically reduced. We have a long way to go in figuring out all the factors that contribute to the development of cancer and in preventing and treating cancer. But that is a far cry from saying that we have made no significant progress in the last four decades.

In addition to Acute Lymphocytic Leukemia, which the author acknowledges as an example of a cancer for which we have seen dramatic progress in treatment and patient outcomes, many other childhood cancers are now curable or can be very successfully treated (1). Overall cancer incidence and mortality are falling due to a combination of efforts aimed at prevention, early detection, and improvements in treatment (2). While some cancers have been resistant to the development of effective therapies, others
have seen dramatic increases in the length and quality of life granted by treatment. The National Cancer Institute regularly reports on trends in cancer diagnosis and treatment, and their data clearly shows significant progress since the passage of the National
Cancer Act in 1971
.

There is no question the dramatic changes in cancer treatment in the early 20th century have largely been replaced by more incremental and less satisfying small improvements, and we all hope for much greater success in the future. But there clearly has been
significant progress in the last 40 years, and it should be noted that it has
all been due to improvements in science-based, conventional therapy, not so-called alternative medical approaches.

2. “People and pets with Stage 3 or Stage 4 metastatic cancer rarely survive.”

This is one of those statements that is trivially true and also deeply misleading. Of course the most advanced cancer has the shortest life expectancy. The whole point of cancer screening and early treatment is to prevent cancers from progressing to these advanced
stages. The implication for a statement like this is, of course, that by using the author’s methods we could do better. As usual, no evidence is provided to support this assertion.

Since I, like the author of this article, am a general practitioner, I asked a colleague, Dr. Gerald Post, who is a veterinary cancer specialist, to address some of the other specific factual claims made in the article. He was kind enough to share his expertise, and here
is what he has to say:

I usually don’t comment on or disparage my fellow veterinarians, but the claims made by this person were so egregious I could not stop my fingers from pounding on my
keyboard.

Claim A:  “most pets with cancer are expected to liver 6-12 months following diagnosis, and that’s ONLY if owners spend thousands of dollars treating the pet with surgery, radiation, and chemotherapy.” HOGWASH! As a veterinary oncologist, all is see, day in day out is cancer. Many of the cancers that I treat have median survival times of 12 months or longer. We recently published a paper documenting that the survival time for dogs with B cell lymphoma treated with our protocol was over 600 days!!!! Median means that 50% of these dogs lived OVER 600 days.

There are many cancers, such as mammary tumors and many skin tumors that don’t ever see an oncologist—not because they die, but because they are very adequately treated by general practice veterinarians. In many cases these tumors are cured by them and don’t even need an oncologist (and for a veterinary oncologist to say he is not needed is saying a lot).

Claim B: “ In my own practice, the average pet with cancer, given a prognosis of 6 to 12 months of life expectancy from conventional veterinarians, typically lives 12 to 24
months or even longer. Additionally, many pets with “incurable” cancers are cured from their cancers using an integrative approach to boost the pet’s immune system, kill cancer cells, reduce the spread of cancer, and detoxify the patient.”

At the risk of repeating myself HOGWASH!!

Where is the proof for any of these statements? As an ethical doctor, if I were to make any of these statements, I would need to have some evidence –aside from my own beliefs—that
the statements were true. After an exhaustive search of the veterinary medical literature, I was unable to find one reference to support any of the assertions made. Immunotherapy is a very valid treatment, don’t get me wrong. The use of IL-2 in dogs with metastatic cancer is documented. Feline interferon can be used to improve the immune response and increase survival in cats infected with feline leukemia.  These very reputable articles, however, make no claims on curing cancer.

Claim C: ”After surgery cuts out most of the cancer, and chemotherapy kills most of the cancer, and radiation burns most of the cancer, what’s left to do destroy any remaining
cancer cells? Absolutely nothing!”

I am assuming that the author just never heard of metronomic chemotherapy or small molecule inhibitors/tyrosine kinase inhibitors. To make the statement that absolutely
nothing can be done post-chemotherapy, radiation therapy, or surgically is
……you guessed it HOGWASH! Metronomic therapy—the use of very low dose cyclophosphamide, an NSAID, as well as doxycycline, has been shown to decrease
the recurrence rate for soft tissue sarcomas, hemangiosarcomas, and theoretically, because it works by inhibiting the in-growth of new blood vessels—something all tumors need to grow larger than 1-2 mm—it can work on any tumor type.

Please make a note that for the claims I am making, I give you the reader and my clients
information based upon documented and peer-reviewed studies. No one is saying that all studies are absolutely factual or that future studies will not refute some claims made by earlier studies. But I am saying that basing my recommendations and claims on evidence IS important. As a reader and as a client you deserve it. When you see a doctor you are relying not only on his or her expertise, but also on the combined knowledge of all the
clinician/scientists in the world!

At the end of the day, the reason why evidence is important is respect! Respect for my clients, respect for my patients and respect for my profession. I truly believe that
those people who seek out cancer treatment for their pets love their pets dearly and are intelligent people, who deserve the best information possible. This empowers them so that they can ultimately make the wisest decision for themselves.

3. Adding “natural remedies” to conventional cancer treatment can prolong life and even cure cancers conventional treatment alone cannot.

This is the core advertising message in the article, and there is not a speck of evidence to show it is true. Substituting alternative medicine for conventional cancer treatment is almost always harmful, as the sad outcome of the NCCAM-funded study of the Gonzalez cancer therapy for pancreatic cancer and many individual anecdotes illustrate. As for adding unproven therapies to conventional treatment, there have been numerous pre-clinical studies and small, low-quality clinical trials published investigating specific alternative therapies used in this way. A few positive results have been reported here and there,, but there is certainly no clear and persuasive body of evidence to show that such an
approach improves quality of life, survival, or any other meaningful, measurable outcome of cancer treatment. This claim is pure ideology and advertising unsupported by solid science. As such, it is at least deeply unethical and at worst false advertising.

Bottom Line

The claims made in this article disparaging scientific cancer therapy and lauding the benefits of adding unproven alternative methods to conventional treatment are unsupported by reliable scientific evidence. Science has made significant progress in
preventing, detecting, and treating cancer and undoubtedly will continue to do
so. This progress has been, and will continue to be due to rigorous, systematic
scientific research. A reliance on tradition, anecdote, personal clinical
experience, and low-quality scientific evidence to justify cancer therapies is
not in the best interest on cancer patients. The good news is that scientific medicine offers real hope for continued improvement in the length and quality of life for cancer patients. The bad news is that some of these patients will be denied the full benefits of scientific medicine and subjected to unnecessary, unhelpful, and sometimes even harmful alternatives if they are misled by sweeping and confident claims unsupported by real evidence. It is our responsibility as doctors to ensure our patients and clients have the full and true facts about their options so they can choose the best possible care for
themselves and their pets.

Posted in General | 12 Comments

Dietary Carbohydrates and Cats: It’s the Calories!

One of the most common questions regarding veterinary nutrition that I get from clients these days is about cats and grains. An argument often made about feline nutrition is that because they are obligate carnivores, cats are ill-equipped to eat carbohydrates and that since commercial diets often include grains and other carbohydrate sources, these must be nutritionally inappropriate for cats. This argument is especially tricky because it is partially correct and partially a fallacy. It is true that cats are obligate carnivores, and diets that exclude all animal products are nearly impossible to make so that they will meet cats’ nutritional needs. On the other hand, there is a significant difference between nutrients in a diet and the ingredients in the diet. Proteins and carbohydrates derived from plant sources can be just as digestible and nutritious for cats as those derived from animal sources. The devil is in the details, and it is usually unwise and inaccurate to make sweeping generalizations about pet nutrition.

A panel of nutrition and feline medicine experts from the American College of Veterinary Medicine (ACVIM) recently drafted a consensus statement on the role of dietary carbohydrates in feline obesity and diabetes which examines some of the evidence concerning dietary carbohydrates and cats. This statement clarifies some questions but also leaves room for debate because it is based not on pure theory and argument but on research evidence, and there are areas in which the research evidence is inconclusive. This sort of ambiguity can be quite frustrating, but it is better to acknowledge the limits of our understanding and work towards expanding them than to simply take the lack of definitive information as an excuse to accept and promote whatever theoretical argument most appeals to us.

The statement was presented at the recent ACVIM annual meeting in the form of a series of questions about dietary carbohydrates in feline diets with brief answers and then an assessment of the strength of the evidence supporting these answers. The statement itself should be published soon, and will doubtless instigate vigorous debate, as it should. I will post a link to the statement and updates as they become available. But for now, here is a summary of the statement as presented at the recent conference.

1. Are dietary carbohydrates an essential or required nutrient for cats?
Answer- No. Based on a good quality and quantity of evidence, most cats do not require dietary carbohydrates. There are some simple sugars in feline milk, so it is possible that nursing kittens may require these but no clear deficiency has been demonstrated.

2. Can cats effectively utilize dietary carbohydrates for energy and nutrition?
Answer- Yes. Based on a good quality and quantity of evidence, cats can effectively digest, absorb, and utilize dietary carbohydrates.

3. Do dietary carbohydrates in the diet cause obesity?
Answer- No. The cause of obesity in almost all cats is excessive calorie intake irrespective of whether the calories come from protein, fat, or carbohydrate. In fact, low carbohydrate foods may be more likely to lead to obesity if they are higher in fat than regular diets.

4. Do dietary carbohydrates contribute to the development of diabetes?
Answer- The consensus was that they do not, however the research evidence is very limited and not always consistent. The consensus was that even if carbohydrates do play a role as a risk factor for diabetes, this is dwarfed by the much more important factor of obesity.

5. Are low-carbohydrate diets useful in the management of feline diabetes?
Answer-Maybe. The evidence is limited and conflicting, and the committee did not achieve a consensus.

The lead presenter summarized the central finding of the panel with three words:

“It’s the calories, Stupid!”

Posted in Nutrition | 7 Comments

From Bloodletting to Evidence-Based Medicine by Dr. Brad Hanna

This is a clear and compelling description of how “Traditional Western Medicine” developed and functioned exactly as much alternative medicine does today, on the basis of tradition and anecdote, and how it was abandoned in favor of scientific medicine. Dr. Hanna illustrates as clearly as I have ever seen why science-based medicine is more reliable than folk medicine, and why it has largely supplanted folk practices wherever there are sufficient resources to make this possible. Bravo Dr. Hanna!

From Bloodletting to Evidence-Based Medicine

Posted in General, Science-Based Veterinary Medicine | Leave a comment

Azodyl for Kidney Failure in Dogs–New Study Finds No Benefit

I have recently summarized the limited evidence concerning the use of Azodyl, a popular probiotic product, for treatment of kidney disease in cats, including a recent study presented as an abstract at the American College of Veterinary Internal Medicine Forum. Another study of this product has also been presented at the same conference.

David J. Polzin, DVM, PhD, DACVIM . Probiotic Therapy of Chronic Kidney Disease

This was a considerably more comprehensive research project, though still with some limitations, as is always true. 32 dogs with moderate kidney failure were randomly assigned to treatment with Azodyl or a placebo. They were otherwise treated identically according to a standardized algorithm for managing kidney disease. They were evaluated in terms of comprehensive bloodwork, body condition, and owner perception of quality of life and 7 time points from 1 month to 1 year after the start of the study. No significant difference in any measure was found between the groups at any time point.

The Azodyl was given as an intact capsule in this study, which eliminated the possible concern about the probiotic organisms being destroyed in the stomach that was raised in the cat study, in which the Azodyl capsules were opened and the product sprinkled on the food. The supplement was also given at twice the manufacturer’s recommended dose. Some of the dogs did have episodes of urinary tract infection during the 12 months of the study and did received short courses of antibiotics, which could potentially interfere with probiotic therapy. But this seems insufficient to entirely invalidate the rather startlingly consistent, negative findings of the study. And since infections are a common and unavoidable problem in kidney failure patients, if the therapy is so easily rendered useless, it would not be of much benefit in the even less controlled conditions of standard clinical use.

Of course, almost no single study should be taken as the final word on any therapy. However, negative results are likely to be more reliable than positive results, and the balance of the evidence is so far pretty negative concerning the usefulness of probiotic therapy for kidney failure. There are theoretical and in vitro study results which suggests that the best one could hope to achieve with probiotic therapy in kidney failure patients is a 10-20% decrease in bloodwork markers of renal failure, which might or might not be sufficient to meaningfully affect the clinical symptoms and the course of the disease. Certainly, in the face of being unable to routinely employ dialysis and transplantation, the most effective therapies available for humans with kidney disease, we should employ any treatment that offers a significant benefit, even a small one. But at this point, it doesn’t look like probiotic therapy holds especially great promise for this disease, unlike some of the other possible conditions in which it might be useful.

In any case, there doesn’t seem to be a strong case for suggesting owners spend their money on this product based on the evidence so far available. And the negative findings so far seen in clinical studies of dogs and cats point out the danger of extrapolating from limited studies in other species. The company-sponsored studies in rats and miniature pigs with artificially induced kidney disease have not proven an accurate indicator of the product’s performance in cats and dogs with naturally occurring kidney failure.

Posted in Herbs and Supplements | 116 Comments

Two Small Studies of Cold Laser Therapy Show Mixed Results for Intervertebral Disk Rupture in Dogs

?

An abstract presented at this year’s American College of Veterinary Internal Medicine reports on a study hypothesizing that low level laser therapy would shorten recovery times in dogs having back surgery for ruptured intervertebral disks and hind limb paralysis.

 

C.C. Williams; G. Barone. Is Low Level Laser Therapy an Effective Adjunctive Treatment to Hemilaminectomy in Dogs with Acute Onset Parapleglia Secondary to Intervertebral Disc Disease? Proceedings, American College of Veterinary Internal Medicine Forum, Denver, CO. June, 2010.

 

I’ve reviewed the evidence for cold laser therapy before, and it is generally of low quality and mixed. Overall, it is possible this therapy could have beneficial effects, but it is far from convincingly demonstrated at this point.

 

I would have expected this small study to find positive results. Of course most studies do regardless of the truth of the underlying hypothesis, which is why preclinical evidence and replication are so critical to effective evaluation of medical interventions. And unfortunately, many investigators and journal editors are reluctant to publish negative results, even though these are the most useful results. So I give these authors great credit for having the intellectual integrity to publish results that do not support their original hypothesis. That is how good science should be done. (Of course, they conclude by suggesting that the negative results were merely an artifact of the small size of the study not truly evidence that their hypothesis was incorrect. Such attempts to put the most positive possible spin on negative results are ubiquitous and probable unavoidable, so that shouldn’t be held against them).

 

The study involved 17 dogs with naturally occurring disease, ruptured intervertebral disks leading to partial or complete hind limb paralysis. All dogs had surgery (hemilaminectomy). They were divided into a group that also received 4 days of laser therapy following surgery and a group that did not. It is not clear if this allocation was random, or if there were any significant differences in the composition of the two groups. These are very important factors in evaluating the meaning of the results.

 

There is also no mention of any blinding, placebo control, or other attempt to control for possible bias beyond utilizing the same pain medication protocol for both groups. This significantly raises the risk of bias in the study. Such bias would almost certainly favor a positive result.

 

In any case, the investigators found no difference in recovery time between the two groups. Given the limited bias controls in the study, this is a bit surprising. Certainly, this small study cannot be taken as definitive regardless of the results. But it is one more bit of evidence to consider in the overall evaluation of the possible uses of cold laser therapy, and a bit which shifts the balance slightly in the negative direction.

 

Update: After this post was published, I became aware of a second, very similar study with different results:

 

W.E. Draper; T.A. Schubert. Low Level Laser Therapy as an Adjunctive Therapy to Thoracolumbar Decompression for Canine Intervertebral Disk Disease.

 

This study followed 36 dogs with acute hind limb weakness or paralysis due to intervertebral disk rupture. These dogs were assigned by alternating allocation to receive standard surgical therapy and post-operative laser therapy or standard treatment only. There was, again, no blinding or placebo control. The outcome measure assessed was the average time until the dogs in each group could walk. Those dogs receiving laser therapy were ambulatory after an average of about 6 days, compared to about 12 days for those not in the laser treatment group.

 

These positive results conflict with those of the other study. Again, positive results are what I would expect from an unblinded and uncontrolled trial, so they must be interpreted cautiously. Though the outcome measure itself is appropriate, it can involve some subjective judgments, and without randomization, blinding, and placebo controls, it is impossible to be certain that the treatment and control groups did not differ in some relevant way other than the treatment under investigation.

 

So from the point of view of an evidence-based analysis of the preponderance of the data, these two studies do little to settle the question of what if any value cold laser therapy might have in intervertebral disk disease. Their different results may be due to differences in patient population, laser treatment technique, or some other factor that obscures the true benefit of laser therapy in the first study. Or, they may differ because the second study was subject to some uncontrolled bias that did not operate in the first. I any case, the question is still an open one, and hopefully as more evidence accumulates we will be able to answer it more clearly.

 

 

 

Posted in General | 10 Comments

Mr. Eric Weisman, Promoter of Evolution Diet, Finally Prosecuted

I initially wrote about Evolution Diet, and its promoter Eric Weisman, in 2009. In my first article, I primarily addressed the  irresponsible and false advertising for the product, and I only touched briefly on Mr. Weisman’s bogus academic credentials and anti-scientific philosophy. Then a few months ago, thanks to information from a reader, I wrote an update which specifically addressed Mr. Weisman’s long history of violating the laws governing his work as a chiropractor as well as those regulating the practice of veterinary medicine. Beyond simply having a unscientific and utterly false set of beliefs about pet health and nutrition, and an egregiously misleading and inappropriate approach to marketing his products, Mr. Weisman was also clearly a scam artist with no regard for the reasonable and appropriate laws governing veterinary and human medicine.

Fortunately, it now appears that finally, almost 30 years after the first action taken against Mr. Weisman in 1982 by the Minnesota Board of Chiropractic, Mr. Weisman will face criminal charges for his actions. According to news reports, he will face 58 counts, including practicing human and veterinary medicine without a license and animal cruelty. I have argued before that the legal system does not effectively control even dramatic cases of quackery and medical fraud, and it is disappointing the Mr. Weisman has been able to continue to profit from taking advantage of sick people and the owners of sick animals for so many decades. But it is encouraging to see him face at least some consequences at last.

The news reports contain some quite horrific examples of Mr. Weisman’s conduct. He allegedly prescribed nutritional and supplement “treatments’ for people with cancer, diagnosed and treated animals with cancer (including some who did not actually have cancer), and consistently falsely represented himself as trained and qualified to diagnose and treat both human and animal illness.

Perhaps the most disturbing story for me as a veterinarian was of a cat Mr. Weisman brought to the veterinary hospital at the University of Minnesota.

Weisman brought in a cat he suspected had kidney failure and cancerous lesions, the complaint said. According to the U’s veterinarian, the cat had neither – it died of pneumonia, was unable to absorb nutrients from the food it ate and had broken bones in each of its front legs. The suspected cancerous lesions, the veterinarian said, were actually scabs caused by the cat walking on its joints instead of its broken feet, the complaint said.

That someone capable of such cruelty could present himself as a public benefactor and a martyr seems inconceivable, but Mr. Weisman’s delusions include just such a perception of himself.

[I am] being attacked because I try to help make a better, more just society. I try to help those that do not have help or are not getting good assistance.

This case illustrates quite starkly the real harm and suffering that can result from irrational and unscientific beliefs about health and disease, and from the actions of individuals who are so blindly committed to such beliefs that they are capable of inflicting terrible harm on those who come to them for help while still seeing themselves as heroes and victims of government and the conventional medical profession.

Posted in General | 36 Comments

Telltale Signs of Pseudoscience

As promised, here is the first tidbit out of Massimo Pigliucci’s Nonsense on Stilts that I want to share. (Technically, it’s not Dr. Pigliucci’s tidbit since he is summarizing part of another book, John Casti’s Paradigms Lost. But Piglucci’s book is where I found it.) These red flags make a nice addition to the various signs of medical nonsense I’ve discussed before (1, 2, 3). Since I have not read the original source for these qualities of pseudoscience, and they were listed but not discussed in detail by Dr. Pigliucci, I may not be interpreting them in precisely the same way as Dr. Casti intended, but they do resonate with my own experiences dealing with proponents of pseudoscience.

1. Anachronistic Thinking: I take this to mean both an inappropriate reverence for the supposed historical longevity of an idea as well as ways of looking at health and disease that come from historical eras before a scientific understanding was possible and that are essentially mythological. Claiming that Traditional Chinese Medicine or acupuncture or some other therapy are thousands of years old (which often isn’t true anyway), and implying that this says something positive about the effectiveness of the approach is an example of anachronistic thinking. So is employing mystical, pre-scientific models of health and disease, such as referring to unmeasurable “energies” as the source of health or illness and the like.

2. Glorification of Mysteries: A mystical perspective often requires that the core truth about something be ultimately unknowable. While science accepts that there is much we do not know, and that there may be things we cannot know, it is fundamentally based on the premise that we can and should try to understand the natural world. If someone tells you health and disease are dependent on mysterious spiritual essences that can never be rationally understood or empirically examined, then you are dealing with pseudoscience.

3. Appeal to Myths: Myths are central to the justification of many pseudoscientific ideas. Fables and other narratives that are unproven or manifestly untrue lie behind non-medical pseudoscience, such as the study of UFOs and cryptozoology, as well as many pseudoscientific theories in medicine. The stories told about toxins in our environment, the mythology about how the natural history of dogs and cats requires them to eat raw diets, the stories about how vaccines and conventional medicines damage the immune system or otherwise do more harm than good, are all examples of myths that are used to justify pseudoscientific approaches to medicine.

4. A Cavalier Approach to Evidence: It is becoming more popular for advocates of pseudoscientific theories, such as homeopathy and homotoxicology for example, to pretend that they are approaching their ideas in an evidence-based manner. However, a closer inspection of their arguments finds an excessive and inappropriate reliance on testimonials, traditions, and other low-quality narrative forms of evidence along with a disdain for clinical trials and pre-clinical evidence. This is not surprising since testimonial narratives are far more likely to appear to validate such approaches than are higher quality forms of evidence.

This goes along with two other characteristics cited by Dr. Pigliucci which seem closely related, “explanation by scenario” and “‘literary’ rather than empirically based interpretations of facts. Pseudoscience is very much an enterprise which tells compelling stories and dresses them up to look like science but which fails to adhere to the methodological core of science, which is objective and systematic collection and analysis of empirical data intended to validate or invalidate the specific predictions of coherent theories about the natural world.

5. Extreme Resistance to Revising One’s Position: Cognitive dissonance is a powerful force in all of us. But pseudoscience as a collaborative social activity is often deliberately focused on maintaining and buttressing beliefs, whereas science is specifically intended to continuously updated and, when necessary, replace its own theories. Science may often be wrong, but as Pigliucci points out, it is always scientists who discover and reveal the errors of other scientists, not those who criticize the scientific enterprise from outside. This emphasis on disproving gives science, unfortunately, an aura of negativity which hampers its public relations. But this is to some extent a function of the very nature of the activity, which is to disprove rather than validate ideas. Negative results are more reliable because our cognitive biases are designed to support and maintain our beliefs. So if a particular medical approach is designed to be self-sustaining and criticism of it is viewed with great hostility (which can so easily and often be seen in the comments posted on this blog), then that approach is likely to be pseudoscience.

6. A Tendency to Shift the Burden of Proof: It is axiomatic in scientific discourse that those who make extraordinary claims bear the burden of providing evidence for these claims. Since pseudoscientific approaches to medicine often lack the support of compelling empirical evidence, advocates for them frequently attempt to shift this burden to critics. It makes no sense, however, to demand that critics prove an implausible idea untrue. If I claim to be the President of the United States, should that claim be automatically accepted unless a skeptic collects sufficient evidence to disprove it, or should I be expected to be the one to prove such an unlikely assertion before it is accepted?

7. Sympathy for a Theory Just Because It’s New or Daring: Pseudoscience is often centered on supposedly new ideas (though these often turn out to be recycled) which lone geniuses claim to have discovered and which mainstream science has somehow overlooked. Often these ideas are dramatic departures from conventional understanding which, if true, would replace the dominant paradigm. It is natural to see such unexpected and dramatic claims as appealing. In America in particular, I think, we have a sympathy for the rebel and the outsider. However, the less exciting reality is that most new ideas, conventional or unconventional, turn out to be wrong. And dramatic revolutions in scientific thinking are uncommon. We simply forget all the new and daring ideas that turned out to be wrong, and remember those few that were eventually validated. This gives us an inaccurate sense of how likely such paradigm shifts are. A hallmark of pseudoscience, then, is what I have elsewhere called the Galileo Complex, in which ideas are viewed positively because they seem new and dramatic.

Posted in General | Leave a comment

Nonsense on Stilts: How to tell science from bunk by Massimo Pigliucci

Massimo Pigliucci is an evolutionary biologist, philosopher, professor, and noted skeptic and author. He is also almost the same age as I am, but I’m trying not to let that ruin my day. His most recent book is Nonsense on Stilts: How to tell science from bunk.

There are many cogent arguments in this book which are relevant and useful for distinguishing between scientific and unscientific or pseudoscientific approaches to medicine, a major goal of this blog. In particular, I found Dr. Pigliucci’s response to postmodernist critiques of science and his discussion of the subject of expertise compelling and enlightening. There are also, however, many other subjects which are interesting in themselves but do not relate directly to the distinction between science and non-science. I began the book with the misapprehension, based on the title and some elements of the advertising and the introduction, that it was intended to be primarily about defining science and distinguishing it from non-science and especially from pseudoscience, which is what I take “bunk” to mean in this context. However, the books reads a bit more like a collection of loosely related essays than a structured argument. The back cover is only half right in that the subject matter is not really a “taxonomy of bunk,” as it is described, but it is an exploration of “the intersection of science and culture at large.”

I will briefly summarize the main points of each section of the book, partly to give a feel for its contents and also to point out those sections that relate to core issues this blog is concerned with. It should be taken as a given that the book itself is far more detailed and nuanced than my attempts to summarize, and that since much of it is well outside my own areas of expertise I may very well unintentionally misrepresent Dr. Pigliucci’s arguments. Since this review is more than long enough by itself, I intend to extract a few specific arguments from the book as subjects for separate posts.

Dr. Pigliucci begins by introducing the “demarcation problem,” the difficulty in distinguishing science from non-scientific or pseudoscientific approaches. He dismisses the popular notion, generally credited to Karl Popper, that science is distinguished primarily by falsifiability, that is one can tell a scientific explanation from a non-scientific one because the former contains criteria by which it can be disproved and the latter does not. I gather from the book that this idea is quite passé in the philosophy of science. But as Pigliucci points out, it is still quite popular among scientists and skeptics, so I would have appreciated a more thorough explanation of why it is inadequate before he moves on to alternative ways of understanding what science is.

The first chapter challenges the usual distinction between so-called “hard” sciences, such as physics, and “soft” sciences like psychology. Pigliucci contends that these two types of scientific endeavor are not really distinguished by the quality, precision, or accuracy of their data but by the degree to which they are predictive or historical. The branches of science usually understood as “hard” are very good at measurement and prediction within controlled conditions but weaker at accounting for more complex “real world” events. The historical sciences, by contrast, can often convincingly explain past events but are not every effective at prediction.

I’m not entirely convinced by this characterization, nor do I see exactly how it leads to what seems to be the main conclusion of this chapter, which is that both approaches deserve the label “science” because they share “the ability to produce and test hypotheses based on systematically collected empirical data (via experiments or observations.)” He returns to this definition in his conclusions, where he defines science this way:

…an investigation of nature, based on the construction of empirically verifiable theories and hypotheses. These three elements, naturalism, theory, and empiricism are what make science different from any other human activity.

This seems a pretty reasonable approach to characterizing science as an intellectual and social endeavor. I’m not entirely sure that the book clearly and logically builds up to this definition, so it seems to appear a bit mysteriously at the beginning and the end and in several places between. This may be my own lack of sophistication in following Dr. Pigliucci’s arguments, but again my impression is that the book is an interesting but meandering stroll through issues associated with science and other elements of culture rather than a forceful linear argument leading up to a final conclusion about what is and is not science.

The next chapter gives several examples of “almost science,” areas of theorizing and research which Dr. Pigliucci doesn’t feel reach the level of full science. The main subjects he uses as examples are string theory and the multiple worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, the Search for Extraterrestrial Intelligence (SETI), and evolutionary psychology. The first apparently fails the test of empiricism in that the hypotheses these theories generate are not yet testable. SETI is characterized as not entirely scientific because it appears not to be falsifiable (negative findings are expected most of the time, so while a single positive finding would justify the endeavor, no number of negative findings could prove the whole thing a waste of time) and because its theoretical foundations are judged weak. Evolutionary psychology as applied to humans is judged insufficiently testable to be solidly scientific, though it may be true science when applied to species which can be observed and manipulated sufficiently to validate or falsify specific hypotheses.

It is clear that Dr. Pigliucci is taking great pains to avoid an overly simplistic application of his defining criteria. He repeatedly reminds the reader that these “almost sciences” are not equivalent to outright pseudosciences like astrology and creationism. Yet there seems to be a degree of subtlety and subjectivity to his assessments that make the value of the whole category of “almost science” a bit questionable. If there are sufficient shades of gray between (almost) universally accepted “real” science on the one hand and (almost) universally accepted non-science on the other, than some significant segment of the continuum in between simply cannot be reliably assessed as science or not science. This may be the intrinsic nature of messy reality, but if our goal is to distinguish science from non-science for important practical reasons, too much nuance and ambiguity undermine that goal.

This is similar to the problem of the reliability of scientific conclusions. It is true, of course, that scientific truths are inherently probabilistic and provisional. But it is also true that once a certain degree of confidence in an idea can be justified by sufficient evidence, doubting such an idea becomes irrational and skepticism becomes willful denialism. In trying to avoid an overly simplistic and rigid set of criteria and in recognizing the inevitable uncertainties in all knowledge, I think Pigliucci sometimes is too careful and undermines the utility of his own, quite reasonable and otherwise useful approach to defining science.

In the next chapter, Dr. Pigliucci discusses several examples of pseudoscience, included HIV/AIDS denialism, astrology, UFOs, and the investigation of paranormal phenomena. While he does a variable job of illustrating why the specific examples are untrue (dissecting astrology in detail but talking mostly about the consequences rather than the factual falsity of AIDS denialism), and he covers many of the usual reasons why people believe in pseudoscience, he doesn’t really use these examples to illustrate a general thesis or approach to identifying pseudoscience and distinguishing it from science.

The next several chapters are interesting in themselves, though  again they really read as a loosely connected set of essays on the relationship between science and society. He discusses how the media (mis)portrays science and scientific information, he talks about the character of the public intellectual and its role in society, he discussed science and politics through the climate change debate, and he looks at the relationship of science and the courts through the example of the intelligent design movement.

There then follows a brief history, in two chapters, of the development of those elements of philosophy that relate to, and eventually become, science. I found this section fascinating, and I enjoyed seeing the development of core ideas underlying modern science portrayed as a historical narrative.

The next three chapters are by far my favorites, and they deal with the subject of expertise, and with the complex but critical issue, from the point of view of science-based medicine, of how we acknowledge the limitations of science and guard against them while at the same time not abandoning science and reason altogether and simply accepting a faith-based approach to knowledge or an epistemologically nihilistic approach like that of extreme postmodernism that says no knowledge is possible. I will be examining Pigliucci’s arguments and conclusions in detail in a future post, because I think he very effectively addresses these issues and points the way to a reconciliation and synthesis that is very useful.

Though I began Dr. Pigliucci’s book with a bit of a misconception of what he was setting out to accomplish, and consequently found only a few sections of it directly applicable to my interest in understanding the distinction between science and non-science, I still found the book interesting and informative. His prose is quite readable, even when dealing with complex issues. I might have preferred a bit less qualification in some areas, but I respect his efforts to present complex and nuanced issues honestly and without oversimplification. Overall, I certainly recommend Nonsense on Stilts.

Posted in Book Reviews | Leave a comment

UK National Health Service Report on Dietary Supplements

I just wanted to draw a little attention to an excellent report just published by the UK National Health Service on dietary supplements for humans.

Supplements: Who Needs Them

This is an excellent, readable summary of the evidence concerning the most common dietary supplements for humans. Covered are:

Multivitamins
Fish Oil
Glucosamine
Echinacea
Zinc for Colds
Weight Loss Supplements
Body Building Supplements
Gingko
Ginseng
Supplements for Aging

Posted in Herbs and Supplements | 2 Comments

Study on Glucosamine for Feline Interstitial Cystitis Does not Suggest any Benefit

A recent research study performed in Thailand has been reported in the American Journal of Veterinary Research (AJVR) which addresses the possibility that oral glucosamine might be useful for treating Feline Interstitial Cystitis (FIC).

Panchaphanpong J, Asawakarn T, Pusoonthornthum R. Effects of oral administration of N-acetyl-d-glucosamine on plasma and urine concentrations of glycosaminoglycans in cats with idiopathic cystitis. Am J Vet Res. 2011 Jun;72(6):843-50.

FIC is a poorly understood condition in which cats experience many of the symptoms of a bladder infection, including blood in their urine and straining to urinate, and which can even lead to urinary tract obstruction in males. For years, such cats were assumed to have bacterial urinary tract infections (UTIs) and treated with antibiotics. Since most were given a 7-10 days course of antibiotics and most got better within that period, it was long believed that the treatment was working and was confirmation of the diagnosis of UTI. This is a classic example of how misleading clinical experience and the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy can be. Eventually, controlled scientific research revealed that the condition is usually inflammatory, not infectious, and typically resolves on its own. Antibiotics don’t help, and since they can cause vomiting, diarrhea, loss of appetite, or wounds on the hands of the person trying to give them to a cat, they are actually more likely to do harm than to help these patients.

Because glycosoaminoglycans (GAGs), like glucosamine, are a normal part of the protective lining of the bladder wall, it has been hypothesized that supplementing with GAGs might be useful in preventing or treating this condition. This paper, however, doesn’t provide much support for that hypothesis.

The study was double-blinded and placebo controlled w/ randomization. There were only 19 cats with FIC (7 in the placebo group and 12 in the glucosamine group), and 10 normal cats were used as controls. The authors gave the treatment group glucosamine (and the placebo group an identical placebo) for 28 days. Blood and urine samples were obtained (though not always from every subject) on the first day before treatment and then at 7, 14, 21, 28, and 56 days after the start of the study. Treatment was discontinued at 28 days.

There were no bloodwork abnormalities in any of the normal or FIC cats. The only difference in urine test results was in the presence of blood in the urine. Before treatment, 6/12 (50%) of the treatment group had no blood in their urine, and at the end of treatment 10/12 (83%) cats in the treatment group were without blood in their urine. In the placebo group, 1/7 (14%) were free of blood before treatment and 5/7 (70%) had no blood in the urine at the end of the 28 days. The authors suggest that because a higher percentage of the treatment group were free of blood in the urine at the end, this suggests the treatment reduced this symptom of FIC. However, no statistical analysis was done to determine if the difference between 83% and 70% is significant, which it may well not be in so small a sample. And a much higher percentage of the placebo group had blood in their urine to begin with, so if anything this group seemed to have a greater improvement over the course of the study than the cats receiving glucosamine.\

Another variable measured was the concentration of GAG in the blood and urine. If GAGs are going to be useful as an oral medication, they have to be absorbed and reached therapeutic levels in the tissue where the problem is. In this study, blood levels of GAG did increase significantly in the treatment group at Days 21 and 28. GAG levels were greater in the treatment group than the placebo group at Day 21, but not at Day 28. And the starting GAG levels in the blood were the same for the normal control cats and for those with FIC. So while it seems the oral glucosamine did increase the blood level of GAG somewhat, it is not clear that blood levels are related to the presence of FIC or that the increase was meaningful since it was not consistently present but only seen at one out of four measurement times.

Another variable measured in the study was the level of GAGs in the urine. Urine GAG levels at the start of the study were higher in cats with FIC than in normal cats. The authors suggest this may be the result of GAG leakage from the inflamed bladder wall in cats with FIC. Urine GAG levels in cats treated with glucosamine were significantly higher than that of cats in the placebo group at only one of the four measurement times, Day 14. The authors imply that this might be a sign of the oral glucosamine reaching the bladder, a necessary prerequisite for the glucosamine having any potential medicinal use for this condition. However, as mentioned the difference only existed at one time point. And if it is true that the FIC cats had higher urine GAG levels than the normal cats at the start of the study because this was a symptom of their diseases, then why are higher levels later interpreted as a potentially positive sign rather than as an indication of greater inflammation and leakage from the bladder wall?

This was a well-designed and conducted study which, as so often happens, was interpreted in a more positive way than really justified by the data reported. Overall, it is consistent with previous studies which suggest that oral glucosamine is probably absorbed to some extent, though it may or may not reach physiologically meaningful concentrations in blood or other tissues. However, there is little indication that the supplement had any significant impact on the FIC affected cats. No clear, consistent effect on clinical symptoms or laboratory measures was observed. The study is useful in investigating in a systematic and generally objective way the potential for oral glucosamine as a therapy for FIC, and by and large it does not suggest there is much value in glucosamine as an FIC therapy.

Posted in Herbs and Supplements | 3 Comments